We believe that the versions of the precautionary principle discussed above are not susceptible to the typical criticisms aimed at positive precautionary principles. They are not overly cautious, they offer significant differences from conventional cost-benefit analyses, and, if applied correctly, they do not lead to contradictory outcomes. However, this does not imply that these interpretations of the precautionary principle are beyond critique. Their initial credibility, at the very least, justifies further examination.
In this section, we aim to highlight a common challenge related to the application of the precautionary principle in the context of germline gene editing (GGE). While it might be assumed that GGE poses credible and significant risks to future generations, suggesting that most reasonable interpretations of the precautionary principle would discourage GGE, this is not necessarily true, as abstaining from GGE could also pose considerable risks to future generations.
As mentioned earlier, one potential benefit of GGE is the elimination of recessive mutations and disease-causing alleles, which could significantly enhance the health of future generations. Conversely, not implementing GGE may indirectly jeopardize their health. Furthermore, Russell Powell has recently posited that if we do not pursue GGE, the genetic health of the population may decline over time, increasing future generations’ reliance on conventional medical interventions. Powell argues that advancements in conventional medicine have alleviated some of the pressures of natural selection, making the human gene pool susceptible to the build-up of harmful mutations. Non-engagement in GGE presents dual risks: first, future generations might need to invest considerable resources to address their compromised genetic health, diverting funds from other avenues to enhance human welfare; second, as they grow increasingly dependent on medical technology for well-being, they may become exceptionally vulnerable to serious consequences if these medical resources become scarce, particularly in the event of a major economic or political crisis. From Powell's perspective, engaging in GGE is a valuable strategy for sustaining current genetic health levels and protecting future generations from severe threats to their well-being.
If Powell's arguments hold true, both pursuing and not pursuing GGE involve risks that could activate many of the aforementioned precautionary principles. Each option presents dire worst-case scenarios, undermines public health security, risks lowering overall well-being, and likely breaches negative obligations to future generations. In this sense, the precautionary principles discussed in this article do not provide clear direction on whether GGE should be pursued.
However, we are not reiterating the common perspective that the precautionary principle can be used both in favor of and against the same policy. While some interpretations can be utilized in this manner, they are susceptible to the incoherence objection discussed earlier in this article and should thus be dismissed. Our contention is that the risks associated with both pursuing and abstaining from GGE appear largely symmetrical, complicating the determination of what course of action the precautionary principle would advocate. Consequently, it remains uncertain whether the precautionary principle would oppose GGE or, contrary to most experts' assumptions, actually support it.
One reason for this uncertainty is our limited understanding of the risks associated with GGE. As gene-editing technologies advance, it may become easier to quantify the relevant risks, which could clarify how to appropriately apply the precautionary principle. For instance, the risks tied to unintended mutations will be better understood as gene editing is implemented across various cell types. Increased knowledge of genetics and genotype-phenotype relationships will illuminate the risks of such mutations. Additionally, intergenerational studies may help quantify the accumulation of germline mutations resulting from modern medicine by tracking mutation rates and genomic locations. Therefore, while it is presently challenging to apply most versions of the precautionary principle to GGE, this difficulty largely stems from knowledge gaps that could be addressed in the future.
Moreover, the precautionary principle does provide relatively clear guidance on one aspect: it suggests preferring certain applications of GGE over others. In particular, the precautionary principles outlined in this article advocate for GGE research aimed at preserving genetic health, enhancing the long-term viability of human populations, or mitigating existential risks, rather than research focused on modifying cosmetic traits or excessively promoting health beyond a sufficient well-being threshold. The latter practices pose unbalanced long-term harm risks to future generations in exchange for short-term gains, while the former do not.
Conclusion:
The precautionary principle is designed to influence decision-making in scenarios where human activities may pose uncertain yet potentially grave threats. This applies perfectly to the ongoing debates around GGE. It is, therefore, surprising that this principle has not garnered more attention in the bioethics discourse surrounding gene editing. Where it has been mentioned, it is often insinuated with little analytical depth that the principle would oppose human germline modification, potentially ruling it out entirely.
We aim to have provided a more nuanced understanding of how various interpretations of the precautionary principle relate to GGE. We argue that, while negative precautionary principles have practical utility in some situations, they contribute little to the policy discussions concerning reproductive GGE. Positive precautionary principles offer more relevant insights. They emphasize the importance of avoiding certain threats, particularly those we tend to undervalue, those that are not well understood, and those potentially impacting a sufficient standard of well-being and health security. Although it is challenging to derive concrete policy recommendations from these interpretations, plausible versions would support GGE in specific contexts, especially where it could address serious genetic mutations or enhance the long-term resilience of human populations. Given that the precautionary principle is predominantly employed against GGE, we believe this perspective is significant.
Much work remains to clarify how the precautionary principle can offer concrete recommendations for GGE. Nevertheless, we hope to have made progress in this article by arguing against outright rejection of the precautionary principle, elucidating its potential role, and highlighting essential questions that must be addressed.